Sunday 18 August 2013

Spotlight: The Communitarian Political Thought of Leonardo Bruni (Florentine Renaissance Humanist)

                Civic humanism, a political ideology developed in Florence, especially by Leonardo Bruni (1370-1444, Chancellor of Florence 1427-1444), was a branch of Renaissance humanism that used ancient sources and humanist principles in order to come out in favour of republican government, particularly Florence’s republican government. Hans Baron argues that the reason for the creation and popularity of Bruni’s civic humanism in Florence was due, in particular, to Florence’s near-annexation by the Duke of Milan, Giangaleazzo Visconti, in 1402. Florence was seen as the one city to stand firm against Visconti’s aggressive tyranny, which bore fruit when Giangalezzo died before he was able to conquer Florence[1]. Leonardo Bruni, in his Panegyric to the City of Florence in 1402, used this event to ‘prove’ that Florence’s foreign policy had always been to preserve liberty in Italy against tyrants and that it was due to the “high morale” of Florence’s republican citizens that Giangaleazzo was defeated[2].  This event helps explain why humanism took on a particularly passionate republican tone in Florence, while it had a more royalist tone in other Italian cities such as Milan or Mantua.
            
           The origins of civic humanism, however, are not to be the topic of this paper. Rather, we seek to examine the contents of the ideology itself through an analysis of Bruni’s political works. Specifically, we will focus on the communitarian and civic nationalist aspects of Bruni’s civic humanism, a crucial aspect of his political thought. This was the idea that the interests of the city collective/community were to be esteemed above the interests of individuals, on the one hand, and above more universalistic notions of morality and justice on the other hand. Bruni uses ancient sources to pinpoint the city as the perfect unit for a community of men. Because of this, he argues that service to the city-collective becomes one of the highest virtues that individuals can strive for. He implies, further, that morally, republican Florence could basically do no wrong to others, because in a way, what served the interests of the Florentine community became, almost de facto, a moral action.
           
           Why was the city the favoured political unit in Bruni’s political thought? First, we must realize that, according to Bruni, the definition of a city is that it be a self-sufficient community: “When it is not self-sufficient it should not be called a city, since it is a property of a city to contain the means of satisfying whatever is required to sustain life”[3]. Using the modern definition of a city as a particular urban area, this is impossible, for doesn’t a city need a countryside to grow food for its inhabitants in order for it to be self-sufficient? And indeed, Bruni identifies not just “artisans” and “warriors”, but also “agriculturists” as the three vital classes of people necessary to form a self-sufficient city[4]. Accordingly, in the Panegyric, Bruni does not confine his praise of Florence solely to urban, metropolitan Florence. He also considers the country houses, walled towns, and the agricultural countryside surrounding Florence to be a key aspect of the Florentine ensemble.  He praises the productive agricultural countryside for making Florence self-sufficient and the walled towns that are like “the stars” surrounding “the moon”, which is Florence[5]. Thus, though the urban, metropolitan city is the most important part of the polity in Bruni’s thought, the polity also includes the surrounding towns and countryside.
           
           In political fact, as Baron argues, the more medieval political order of Trecento Italy “with fragmented local allegiances but a universal allegiance either to emperor or pope” had given way in the Quattrocento to “a system of sovereign region-states each of which had absorbed the abundance of local autonomies”[6]. It was the regional city-state of Florence that Bruni took as his ideal political community. To justify this choice, Bruni, as noted above, defined cities, with Aristotle and his followers, in his notes on his translation of the pseudo-Aristotelian economics, as a “common society” whose inhabitants, when pooled together, “can have enough to support a good standard of living” and who “live under the same laws”[7]. This is why he made the point in the Panegyric that Florence and its countryside were self-sufficient, making them “independent of outside help either for necessities or even for luxuries”[8]. Of course, this assertion was in no way true. Florence at that time relied heavily on international banking and the international wool trade for its great wealth. Nevertheless, Bruni had to claim that Florence was self-sufficient in order to legitimize it as the perfect community of men, the polis of the ancient Greeks. By doing so, he was able to justify making the interests of this particular collective supreme in his political thought.
            
           Having identified his favoured political collective, Bruni had to define the proper relationship between this collective and the individual, and between this collective and other, rival political collectives. Starting with the individual, Bruni often hinted that he saw the individual mainly as an instrument to serve the interests of the city collective. Of course, in Bruni’s original justification of the city as supreme collective, he mentions that cities are formed in order to enable individuals to live well. Nevertheless, because the city collective is such an important component of the general happiness of individual citizens, its preservation and interests, in Bruni’s thought, becomes even more important than the preservation and interests of individuals themselves. This idea is expressed in the following passage: “Since without cities there is no life for human beings, devotion to country and the acceptance of death for its salvation are praised to the skies”[9]. And again: “Foremost honor is deservedly given to his native land, for that is the first and prerequisite basis of human happiness, to be put as object of veneration ahead even of parents.”[10].

This theme appears in Bruni’s History of the Florentine People too, where Bruni claims that Giano della Bella, the leader of those agitating for the Ordinances of Justice, criticized the Florentine people who “kept letting individuals suffer injustice” and who “failed to realize that they were all as a group being threatened by shameful servitude”[11]. By contrast, once the Ordinances were passed, the Florentine people exercised their collective power by joining the first post-Ordinances Standard-Bearer of Justice, Baldo Ruffoli, in exiling and destroying the properties of the clan of a noble who murdered a common citizen[12]. In Bruni’s historical narrative, when individuals cared only about themselves, they were ripe to be assaulted and enslaved by violent noblemen, but when they came together as a collective, they were able to amass enough power to protect their lives, liberty, and property from their rapacious enemies.
             
           This idea also shaped Bruni’s ideas concerning the accumulation of wealth. In general, Bruni was far friendlier towards the accumulation of wealth than his medieval predecessors. In the Preface to his translation of the Economics, Bruni says that: “Wealth is indeed useful, since it is both an embellishment for those who possess it, and the means by which they may exercise virtue”, and then says that: “Therefore for our own sakes, and even more for love of our children, we ought to strive as far as we honorably can to increase our wealth, since it is included by the philosophers among the things that are good”[13]. It would appear that Bruni has adopted a fairly individualistic, or at least family-oriented, view of the virtues of accumulating wealth here, but in his political orations, he takes a different stance. In his Oration for the Funeral of Nanni Strozzi, Bruni brags about the wealth of Florentine citizens, but then says: “Evidence of it (Florence’s great wealth) is this long Milanese war which has been waged at incredible cost, in which we are spending over thirty-five hundred thousand (florins), and nevertheless men are prompter in paying their levy now when the war is drawing to a close than they were at is beginning”[14]. The relevant evidence of Florentine wealth for Bruni is here their ability to spend on collective endeavours, not individual gratifications. Bruni chooses not to brag about the luxuries that Florentine patricians can enjoy or the rich estates that Florentines are able to leave to their children. Rather, it is the promptness in paying taxes for a war effort of the city collective that receives Bruni’s praise.

It may be objected that in the Panegyric, Bruni talks about the interior and exterior beauty of Florentine buildings, perhaps indicating that he does praise wealth for its ability to buy luxuries[15]. However, he does so in the context of praising Florence as a whole, rather than in order to praise the good taste and wealth of individual Florentines. Bruni uses the beauty of Florentine buildings as a praise of Florence as a collective, over other, rival, city collectives. Bruni interprets city beautification not as an individual affair, but as a collective affair, concerning the pride of the whole city. Thus, in his political works at least, the accumulation of wealth, and individual endeavours in general, are primarily to be instruments for advancing the welfare of the city as a collective entity.
            
           What of the relationship in Bruni’s thought between Florence, Bruni’s favoured collective, and other political collectives? In the Panegyric Bruni writes: “Therefore, to you, also, men of Florence, belongs by hereditary right dominion over the entire world and possession of your parental legacy (because they were descended from the Romans and carried on their spirit). From this it follows that all wars that are waged by the Florentine people are most just, and this people can never lack justice in its wars since it necessarily wages war for the defense or recovery of its own territory”[16]. This passage is quite bombastic and, admittedly, Bruni takes a more moderate stance in other places, but it suggests his general attitude towards the perennial justice of his collective’s cause. Later on in the Panegyric, Bruni asserts that Florence has always kept all its promises to other states and that its primary goal was always to preserve the liberty of the states of Italy[17]. Thus, Bruni did not really advocate that Florence conquer the whole world and excuse this by claiming some shadowy inheritance rights from ancient Rome, as the first passage quoted might suggest, but at no point does he assert that anything republican Florence did in its foreign policy was unjust.
            
           A good example of this is in Bruni’s letter he wrote as chancellor, justifying Florence’s 1429 invasion of Lucca, A Rebuttal of the Critics of the People of Florence for the Invasion of Lucca. Bruni writes: “I wish therefore to state that the invasion of Lucca, until the people of Florence decided upon it, was something I did not favor, and always counselled against; not, however, because I thought it unjust or dishonorable, but because wars entail such evils, desolations and other great misfortunes that the very thought of them causes me instinctively to hold them in horror and to seek to avoid them. Yet, when the decision was made, it was my duty and that of every citizen to accept what the city had decided and ordained”[18]. In this passage, Bruni expresses his personal disapproval of the war, but quickly reassures us of two things. First, that the war could not possibly be unjust, even though you would think that the justice of something that involved “evils, desolations and other great misfortunes” would at least be questioned for that reason alone. Second, that even though he was personally opposed, once the city collective had decided something, it was his duty as an individual to put away his misgivings and support the city wholeheartedly. This suggests that for Bruni, the justice of something that the city collective had decided was unquestionable. Another passage, from De Militia, lends support to this view: “we should consider man’s true duties only those which have been established by its (the city’s) constitution and ordinance”[19]. Conspicuously absent from this statement is the religious view that man’s primary duties are assigned by God or that man has certain moral duties to his fellow men, regardless of which political collective they belong to. Rather, the city collective becomes the ultimate source of men’s duties, and thus of justice as well.
            
           Another example of Bruni’s city-centered conception of justice is found in De Militia. He says that the main function of the warrior, or miles, is to defend citizens against evil[20]. Bruni says that the miles should not just defend citizens against evil coming from foreign powers, but he should also “help his country by word and deed when it is being troubled by wicked citizens” by protecting the weak against the aggression of the strong[21]. However, Bruni also praises Romulus for attaching great importance to his armed forces, or militia, confirmed in Romulus’s supposed last words to Julius Proculus: “tell the Romans it is the will of the gods that my Rome should be the capital of the world. Let them therefore cultivate and master the art of the military, and pass it on to their posterity, so that no human power will be able to resist Roman arms”[22]. Despite what Bruni says about the miles being defenders of citizens against evil, he praises the attitude of a ruler who wanted to strengthen the militia in order that his city could become lord of the world, hardly a defensive undertaking. The paradox is resolved however, when we realize that Bruni assigned to the miles the duty of protecting their own citizens against evil, he said nothing about any other collective’s citizens. In Bruni’s thought, the warriors, like other citizens, have duties only to their particular city collective, not to God or to a more universal morality or justice. This allows them, without contradiction, to defend their own citizens against evil, while aggressing against the citizens of other political collectives, because they owe these outsiders no protection.
               
           Thus, the idea that the perfect political collective was the city-state and that both the individual citizen and more universal considerations of morality and justice should be subordinate to the interests of this city collective was an important aspect of Leonardo Bruni’s civic humanist political thought. This communitarian worldview would take a place beside the more religious, Christian-universalist worldview characteristic of medieval thought and the more individualist worldview that would later emerge in the thought of some Enlightenment and classical liberal thinkers in the array of Europeans’ potential political philosophies. As such, an elucidation of this aspect of Bruni’s thought helps place him, as a political thinker, within the broader trajectory of European intellectual history.
             
           
              
               



[1] Hans Baron, The Crisis of the Early Italian Renaissance (Princeton : Princeton University Press, 1955), 33.
[2] Leonardo Bruni, “Panegyric to the City of Florence,” in The Earthly Republic, ed. Benjamin Kohl and Ronald Witt, trans. Benjamin Kohl (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1978), 165-167.
[3] Leonardo Bruni, “On Knighthood (De Militia),” in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, ed. Gordon Griffiths, James Hankins, David Thomson, trans. Gordon Griffiths (Binghamton, New York: Centre for Medieval and Early Renaissance Studies State University of New York at Binghamton, 1987), 129.
[4] Bruni, De Militia, 129.
[5] Bruni, Panegyric, 144-145.
[6] Baron, 9.
[7] Leonardo Bruni, “Bruni’s Translation and Notes on the Economics: Bruni’s Notes to Book I, Chapter 1,” in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, 309.
[8] Bruni, Panegyric, 145.
[9] Bruni, De Militia, 130.
[10] Bruni, “Oration for the Funeral of Nanni Strozzi,” in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, 123.
[11]Leonardo Bruni, History of the Florentine People ,vol I, trans. James Hankins (Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press, 2001), 361.
[12] Bruni, History of the Florentine People Vol I, 373.
[13] Leonardo Bruni, “Preface to Book I of the Aristotelian Treatise on Economics, or Family Estate Management, addressed to Cosimo de’ Medici,” in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, 305-306.
[14] Bruni, Oration for the Funeral of Nanni Strozzi, 127.
[15] Bruni, Panegyric, 140.
[16] Bruni, Panegyric, 150.
[17] Bruni, Panegyric, 161, 165-166.
[18] Leonardo Bruni, “A Rebuttal of the Critics of the People of Florence for the Invasion of Lucca,” in The Humanism of Leonardo Bruni, 146.
[19] Bruni, De Militia, 128.
[20] Bruni, De Militia, 131.
[21] Bruni, De Militia, 139-140.
[22] Bruni, De Militia, 134-135.

No comments:

Post a Comment